Thursday 4 March 2021

ESSAY: AN EXAMINATION OF RESPONSIBLE ACTION IN THE “ROMAN PLAYS”: TITUS ANDRONICUS AND CORIOLANUS by William Shakespeare

 

HERE IS AN ESSAY I WROTE AT UNI in the Early Holocene. It goes into the weeds a bit, but makes a couple of good points I thought the reader might take along with them.

Cheers, Jake.

 

IN THE INTRODUCTION TO HIS BOOK, SHAKESPEARE'S TRAGIC COSMOS, Thomas McAlindon states that Shakespeare had a “fundamentally traditional” (4) understanding of nature. By “traditional”, McAlindon suggests that many Renaissance thinkers, including Shakespeare, kept their belief in a system that was developed in Classical Greece and was adopted by Europe during the Middle Ages, even as it's tenets were being challeged by new formulations of nature then emerging in scientific circles. 

This system was two-fold: One part consisted of a hierarchical ordering of the universe; the other part consisted of a “dynamic system of interacting, interdependent opposites.” (5).

"In the first part, the hierarchical order of the universe gave everything a fixed place and identity. It ordered everything at both a macrocosmic level and a microcosmic one, an order that extended from the stars down to the physical elements of the earth."

 

It was commonly known as the “Great Chain of Being”. This “chain” was seen to extend from God, downward, through the heavenly ranks of angels, into the star-filled universe, to the planets, to man, to the animals, plants and so on. The lower “links” of the chain were inferior and subject to the ones above. Animals, for example, were inferior to man. There was thought to be a human order to the chain, as well, with the lowest links in the chain corresponding to the lowest levels of feudal society, then ascending, link-by-link, to the highest level represented by the king. From there, the chain ascended upward, to God. This system proved helpful in rationalizing the status quo of feudal society, but it also provided a sense of stability to man’s conception of the universe and his place in it. It acted to “knit” the macrocosm with the microcosm: What was conceived at the level of the stars as the fundamental order of things was mirrored in the conceptions of society and earthly nature.

The second part of this system was a structure of opposites or “contrariety” (9) that operated within the hierarchy to establish ranking and to maintain the order of the chain. Both parts, McAlindon states, were “treated as twin aspects of universal order” (5), but this second structure helped to provide an understanding of the actions and processes that were observed to occur in the universe. In such a scheme, the universe was seen to operate on a grand scale of checks and balances, with one element, or attribute, or process acting upon its opposite. This action resulted in a state of equilibrium for that element (or attribute or process). For example, the heat of a fire acted upon the cold of the air surrounding it to affect its (the air’s) mean temperature. The cold of the air, in turn, acted upon the heat of the fire to affect the fire’s mean temperature. Whereas today, science would explain this phenomenon in terms of a chemical reaction, Medieval and early Renaissance thinking had it that “hotness” was a quality separate from “coldness” and each, because they were opposed, acted upon the other.

In terms of the physical world, we see this system suggest, for example, that water, by its nature, is contrary to air, and this was the reason they remained separate. Again, modern science would suggest chemistry as the reason. Or in terms of processes, the process of decay was opposed to the process of growth and was therefore “acting” upon it. This system operated, as well, on the level of the human psyche as found in the theory of opposing and counterbalancing “humors” (choler, melancholy, blood, and phlegm).

On the human level, this system helped to explain how people arrived at decisions and why they acted in the manner they did. Human characteristics such as nobility, love, honour, and respect existed alongside their opposites. Each opposite acted upon the other to establish a “mean” or equilibrium. Furthermore, while each characteristic operated ideally around its own mean, this balance was by no means a given. Each characteristic could swing like a pendulum away from its mean and toward its opposite. An excessive sense of nobility, for example, could “swing” this characteristic away from its optimal level and toward its opposite. I will return to this idea in more detail later.

 

For this essay, I will use McAlindon’s concept of “contrariety” to suggest how Shakespeare develops the idea of responsible action for his characters. Several characters will be examined as to how they make their decisions, and whether there is a common theme running through their actions. I suggest there is, and I will begin exploring it by examining Shakespeare’s first tragedy, "Titus Andronicus". 

 

THE PLAY BEGINS with a portrayal of civil strife. The old emperor is dead and, with no designated heir to the throne, his two sons, Saturninus and Bassianus, vie for power. The traditional process of transferring the crown to the eldest son is challenged by the younger. The play opens with the two brothers each calling for support from their followers as they make their case to become the next emperor. It is interesting that both Saturninus and his brother use the phrase “of my right” (I.i.1; 9). Each claims the throne is theirs by right. Of course, the question is who does have the right to the throne? In the time when the play is set*, during or just after one period of conflict in the Gothic Wars, Rome is past its peak. The long decline has begun and with it come challenges to long-standing traditions and precedents. The elder Saturninus’s call for his supporters to take up arms for his cause, based on the precedent of primogeniture, is matched by Bassianus’s appeal, that his followers “fight for freedom in your choice” (I.i;17).

It is also interesting to note to whom each brother appeals for support. Saturninus appeals first to the “noble patricians [and] patrons” (I.i.1) of Rome, and then almost as an afterthought, to his “countrymen, my loving followers” (I.i.3). Bassianus, on the other hand, appeals directly to to “Romans, friends, followers, favorers” (I.i.9), to the common people of Rome. Saturninus asks, first and foremost, for support from traditional sources of power—the rich elites, and his political and financial backers, his “patrons”. Bassianus appeals to the wider Roman population to help him win the crown through a “pure election” (I.i.16).

Here we are presented with opposites. One brother appeals to tradition, the other for change. The pattern of contrariety, discussed earlier, appears here in the opening lines of the play, and reflects the social strife of a divided Rome. Both brothers claim they have the “right” to the crown. Both appeal to different factions within the Roman population for support. How will the situation be resolved? Will there be a return to equilibrium with a peaceful transition of power? Or will there be civil war?

Enter Tribune Marcus Andronicus—immediately—holding the imperial crown. Marcus comes between the two brothers, these two extremes, not as a mediator, but rather, as a bond uniting them: He provides a “mean” point, a balance. In terms of the plot, he provides a third alternative for the crown—his own brother, Titus, a respected general recently returned from a successful military campaign fighting the Goths. By coming between the two brothers as he does, Marcus both unites them to a common, ‘middle ground’ purpose, and at the same time allows them to remain separate and intact: one extreme does not supersede or absorb the other. McAlindon says of this role of the mean:


"The bond which simultaneously unites the opposites in nature and keeps them apart was thought of as a mean between extremes; thus Aristotle founded his whole ethical theory on the idea of virtue as a mean between the opposites of excess and deficiency." (19-20, McAlindon).

 

Thus, by presenting the mean between two political extremes, Marcus provides an example of contrariety at a societal level. (Titus will appeal to the Roman people through their Tribunes to choose Saturnius as the next emperor which will leave the political state of Rome once more imbalanced.**) And of course, it operates on the personal, as well. For example, an individual’s love can swing like a pendulum, from extreme to extreme when it does not operate at its mean. Love can swing from compassion to obsession, from sensuality to narcissism. Moreover, the process of contrariety operates on other human attributes: honour, loyalty, nobility, gentleness, and so on.

It can transform someone into a hero, or it can degenerate him into a state of murderous revenge. In the latter case, as we will shortly see, Titus will be carried to such an extreme.

This system of duality, of nature based on opposing extremes, has what McAlindon calls a “horizontal rather than vertical” (19) view of the self. He suggests it is not the case of lower or baser instincts supplanting the higher, more virtuous ones. Rather, it is a case of all the instincts (or virtues or characteristics) operating within their own means or limits. Problems arise when one or the other goes beyond its boundaries and becomes unbalanced. Such a system contrasts with the Christian concept of human nature as a battle between virtue and vice. Instead, all our human attributes are seen to operate (optimally) at their mean points, with opposing attributes located, not below or above, but alongside each other, on the same continuum. 

Unlike the Christian perspective, in this Classical scheme, virtue and vice exist, if not as equals, at least as equal “competitors”. As an example, excessive love can swing or move to its opposite. Love can move like a bar of colour moves from white into various shades of grey, and finally into ever-deepening black. Titus’ love moves in such a manner. We witness his grief over the murders of his children as it carries him further and further into a state that resembles the opposite of love, and it is out of this state that he commits his bloody excesses of revenge. The significant point to remember is that Titus’s actions begin from a state of love and move to its opposite. To make this point clear, we must examine love according to its mean.

 

To suggest there is a mean for love is to suggest there are also extremes of love. To love someone involves an emotional commitment, and an array of actions and activities around and for the loved one. The question to ask is which actions are appropriate, and which are not. Titus’s actions can be examined in light of love’s mean. The central question of Revenge Tragedy (and "Titus" is a play that draws heavily on revenge drama motifs) is, of course, whether the extreme of revenge is justified at any time. Does Titus’s love for his children in any way justify his actions?

This complex scheme of checks and balances between the extremes of opposites; this system of contrariety that places virtue and vice on the same continuum helps us to understand the sense of moral ambiguity often found in Shakespeare’s plays. Take for example the character of Aaron. What does Shakespeare want us to make of him? Do we conclude that he is a good man gone bad, or that he is simply evil or insane? How are we to judge his character? The point is that Shakespeare deliberately leaves unresolved any final interpretation of his character. (Similarly, characters such as Iago or Richard III, or other dramatists’ creations, such as Middleton’s and Rowley’s Deflores, for example, or Marlowe’s Barabbas, also leave us feeling that simple condemnation of them is inadequate, if not inappropriate.)

 

Shakespeare seems to suggest with characters such as Titus that human nature is not so much a contest of good versus evil, but rather it is a question of a balance between good and evil. He explores problems that arise when both virtue and vice become excessive and stray from their means, and go beyond their bounds. The sense is that evil is as much a part of the human personality as good is, but balance is what keeps everything in check.

To return to the play’s first scene, it is interesting to note that Bassianus is seen to grant the authority of the crown, unreservedly, to Titus as the compromise choice. He says:

 

That I will here dismiss my loving friends;

And to my fortunes and the people’s favour

Commit my cause in balance to be weigh’d. (I.i.53-55).

 

Bassinanus’s use of “balance” and “weigh’d” are significant here because they suggest the mean that we have been examining. They suggest that Bassianus has achieved a balance. His decision to allow Marcus to arbitrate the succession question reflects a state of calm and reasoned deliberation. On the other hand, Saturninus dismisses his followers, saying:

 

I thank you all and here dismiss you all,

And to the love of favor of my country

Commit myself, my person and the cause. (I.i.58-59).

 

He goes on to say in lines that foreshadow the tragic events to come:

 

Rome, be as just and gracious unto me

As I am confident and kind to thee.

Open the gates and let me in. (I.i.60-62).

 

Saturninus does not commit his cause to fortune to be “weigh’d” as does Bassianus. Instead, he commits himself, as an individual and a “person” (a royal figure) to the “love and favor” of his country. He seems here to have abstracted himself into two parts—his private self (“myself”) and his public self (“person”). He commits both, along with a third, “the cause”, to the people. But the cause is not even his, as suggested by his use of the definite article “the” (it is not "my cause"); it is something that has grown beyond merely his personal commitment and has become idealized, abstract. As well, that he addresses “Rome” in a kind of apostrophe suggests a further level of abstraction. While Bassianus speaks directly to the people listening to him, Saturninus seems to distance himself from his audience. It is not appropriate for him to address "Rome", the city, as if it were a god that could respond to his prayer. In pagan Rome, Jupiter was the patron diety of the city who would be called upon in such a manner. That Saturninus calls upon the city instead of its people (or even appealing to the gods of old to decide who will be emperor), again suggests he has an inappropriate level of abstraction. Which begs the question: to whom is he 'loyal'? Is it to the people of Rome? To the city's patron god? Or to some abstract notion he has, some ideal that has no basis in reality?  The people of Rome stand before him; he should address them. He seems to hold an idealized view  of Rome, one that is far more "balanced" and harmonious than currently exists.

At this point in its history, the imperial city is factionalized, its leadership in crisis, its citizens divided in their support. The “Rome” Saturninus addresses does not exist in reality. To return Rome to a state of political equilibrium, Saturninus needs to deal directly and practically with its people who are listening to him. That he fails to understand this essential requirement indicates his own imbalanced nature, his own extreme state. 

Bassianus, on the other hand, is aware of the crisis. He will allow the choice of succession to be determined by fortune and the people of Rome, as he accepts Marcus's proposal of Titus as the new emperor. 

 

While Saturninus has adopted an inappropriate level of idealization in his thinking Titus, ironically, will be seen to adopt an even greater level in his as the play develops, with bloody and tragic results. But at this point, it should be noted there are several words used by Marcus to describe Titus, that would normally suggest positive, even admirable, character traits: words like” “nobler”, “honor” and “good” (I.i.25; 34; 37). These words convey a sense of virtuousness, and we would normally assume that virtuous acts come from someone so described. While Titus does indeed act virtuously out of a sense of honour, it is because he carries honour to an extreme, that this positive virtue in him, in fact dishonours him. His idealized understanding of honour (just as with Saturninus and his idealized sense of a “cause”) becomes so extreme that he excludes all other considerations in his decision-making. For example, in the unnecessary sacrifice of Tamora’s son, Titus acts with “[i]rreligious piety” (I.i.130). His piety, that he was praised for by his brother Marcus in the opening scene, has become its opposite, as Tamora’s bitter exclamation suggests. If we use our system of contrariety here, we see that Titus’s honour has become unbalanced and has ‘swung over' to its opposite. His sacrifice of Alarbus and the slaying of his own son suggest his honour has moved away from its balanced “mean” to an extreme of cruelty. His preoccupation with abstractions like honour, his family name, his respect for the dead, while they are worthy characteristics (as is Saturninus’s ideal of Rome), nevertheless are not counterbalanced by other considerations, such as Tamora’s appeal for simple human mercy. We see Titus as a pendulum, with ever-increasing arcs: His extremes will increase until he passes the bounds of sanity into madness.

    Lawrence Olivier "Titus"
The idea that it is Titus’s honour that causes him to act with such cruelty is one which suggests a non-Christian view of the self. His honour, by being extreme and unbalanced, moved along the continuum to its opposite. This “horizontal” system of the self, as McAlindon terms it, does not seem to allow for the presence of a deity in its scheme. In both "Titus Andronicus" and "Coriolanus" (which we will look at next), we do not have a sense of God’s presence (or Jupiter’s or some other god as a “final arbiter” of things). We get, instead, the sense of a complex, natural system functioning at the highest and lowest levels of the universe. There is no final judgement or moral assurance at the end of these plays, as there are, in Medieval Morality plays or Mystery Cycles, for example. Instead, we are left with questions. What caused the disorder? Why did one solution fail while another succeeded? Will the new order last? We are not given the promise that all will be well. In such a system, the processes of checks and balances, of opposites and their means, is ongoing. It does not end conclusively, nor does it end cleanly. The natural processes of the world are constantly being balanced and re-balanced, just as are the moral choices of humanity.

To return to the play, Shakespeare provides a powerful example of this duality  (of nature being composed of opposites) in his descriptions of the forest in Act II. For Aaron, the forest is a place ‘[f]itted by kind for rape and villainy” (II.i.116). It is “ruthless, dreadful, deaf and dull” (II.i.128). But for Tamora, the forest is a sensual delight where:

 

Birds chaunt melody on every bush

The[snake] lies coiled in the cheerful sun,

The green leaves quiver with the cooling wind (II.iii.12-14).

 

In the woods, beauty and delight are side by side with ugliness, danger, and death. The suggestion is that such equilibrium can quickly change. Tamora’s “sweet shade” (II.iii.16) can in an instant become the evil gloom envisioned by Aaron. (But, of course, the opposite is also true.) Tamora’s view of the forest is held in place by a precarious and complex system of checks and balances.

This system of contrariety we have been looking at is helpful in the analysis of “evil” characters such as Aaron. Aaron ("The Moor") is unrepentantly evil: He plots the rape and mutilation of Lavinia, and similarly, the deaths of Bassianus, Quintus and Martius. He murders Tamora’s nurse. His relationship with Tamora is one he uses to further his own ends. We condemn him for all of this, and yet we praise him for saving the life of his son. With this contradiction in mind, what can we say about Aaron? Is he evil? When Aaron says he would have “done a thousand dreadful things, / As willingly as one would kill a fly,” (V.i.141-42), we again condemn him for such a wish. At the same time, we compare his statement with the Act III scene that has Titus kill a fly. The suggestion is that the two are somehow connected, that there is complicity in their actions; after all, both men conspire and commit murder. However, when we compare their acts, it must be remembered that Titus’s own deeds of revenge, in terms of their ferocity, far exceed those of Aaron. Aaron’s singular act of murder is done as a matter of “policy” (IV.ii.148). This suggests that if "policy" had dictated otherwise then he would not have murdered the nurse. Interestingly, Aaron stabs her and then likens her to a “pig prepared to the spit” (IV.ii.146) which echoes the horrific dinner Titus plans in Act V. However, Aaron is not seen to revel in his deed, as Titus does; chance and a quick policy decision, have formed his act.

Shakespeare, then, is suggesting that to label Aaron as evil is too simple. After all, Tamora is an adulteress, and her two sons were already predisposed to rape and violence before Aaron began to manipulate them. The point being, it's not as if Aaron has corrupted 'the virtuous'. The sense is that Aaron’s evil nature is partly a result of imbalances exhibited by the people around him and in his newly-adopted society. His litany of evil in Act V is also interesting. Here he lists the misdeeds he has accomplished in the past and ones (some bizarrely comic) he wishes he could have done if he'd had the time: such as putting dead people on neighbour’s porches; causing cattle to break their necks; setting fire to bars and so on. His listing of evil takes on an almost incantatory, mystical, quality that seems more a part of some malevolent, natural force than something coming from an individual person. (I'll also state that Aaron's evil has an absurd quality to it, a mawkishness, that suggests a pendulum swing from the logical--his "policy"--to the absurd; i.e. another 'imbalance'.) This is the point Shakespeare wishes to leave with us: Aaron’s evil comes from a complex process of checks and balances operating within the Moor and those around him. It is not simply a matter that Aaron is evil. How he arrives at such a state is equally important.

 

    Anthony Hopkins "Titus"
Then there is the question of authority. With no deity to appeal to in this system of checks and balances, no ultimate arbiter, to whom does one ask permission for one’s actions? Who does Titus ask as he plots his final revenge? Who is there who will “authorize” his murders? Traditional Revenge Tragedy motifs have such appeals going to either society for social justice; to heaven for divine retribution; or to hell (or nature, in the sense of natural forces rising to destroy the evil doer). Marcus swears to the memory of “Lord Junius Brutus” (IV.i.91) as a kind of appeal to authorize their revenge. Titus, as he descends into madness, shoots arrows into the sky with appeals to the gods for justice. There are also references to ancient Troy and to stories from Ovid. These references and stories are sources of authority for Titus: they show him how he should act. They are a kind of literary or historical guide. Livy’s story of Virginius is used by Titus to guide his actions in Act V. However, he “misreads” the tale, which is one that involves a father murdering his daughter before she is raped to protect her virginity and thus save her honour. Titus misreads Livy (his appeal) and this is significant because it reminds us of the imbalance that has occurred within him—he has slipped into madness.

If we compare Titus's son, Lucius, to Titus, we see in him a contrasting balance. For example, he steps between Saturnius and Titus, just as his uncle Marcus did, and clarifys a misunderstanding Saturnius had with respect to Titus's intentions, preventing possible bloodshed in the heat of the moment. But at the beginning of the play, Lucius’s demand for a blood sacrifice for his dead brothers is seen as excessive and cruel (at least for a modern audience; Elizabethans may have felt more sacrifices were needed.) We judged him then as we now judge Titus and Saturninus: as operating from an abstract set of ideals instead of a balanced sense of humanity. However, by the play’s end, it is Lucius who brings stability to Rome, and it is interesting that he has had to travel to the Goths (murderers of his brothers, his city’s enemy, its ‘opposite’ and his, as well) in order to establish his own equilibrium, and to bring that balance back to Rome. His enlistment of Goth soldiers in his pursuit of justice in Rome suggests a bridging of opposites on a societal level. And we see his sense of balance and proportion acting on a personal level when he responds to Aaron’s confession. When he learns his family has suffered because of Aaron, he responds—not with bloody revenge as Titus will at his banquet—but as a statesman, sparing Aaron’s child and reserving his punishment for later.

 

 

IN THE PLAY "CORIOLANUS" THERE IS A SIMILAR OPENING SCENE  depicting internal strife as we saw in "Titus Andronicus". General Coriolanus, like Titus, is at odds with Rome. but here, he is at odds with the body politic of Rome (while Titus was involved in a bloody, personal feud with his extended family.) The citizens of Rome are in near revolt over what they claim are the harsh policies of Coriolanus. They claim his policies keep them hungry. They claim he is proud and self-centered. They question his motivations for serving Rome in its wars. They claim he acted merely to “please his mother” (I.i.39). In discussing "Coriolanus", I will continue to use McAlindon’s “contrariety” model to analyze characters’ motivations and actions, and I would also like to first examine two major motifs that occur in the play: “body” and “name”.

Beginning with the body motif: in "Coriolanus", the Roman population as ‘a body’ is more evident than in "Titus". We witness several public scenes suggesting large gatherings; the plebeian representatives Sicinius and Brutus play important, if minor, roles and there is much presentation of plebeian dialogue. Menenius’s speech, in which he depicts Rome as a body with its parts in conflict with each other, is another example. And throughout the play there are scenes of eating and feasting. What are we to make of all these references to the body and its functions? I think it is evident that Shakespeare is asking us to compare the body of the state with the body of Coriolanus. By Act II, we are aware of the physicality of Coriolanus: of his explosive temper, of his efforts on the battlefield, with Menenius recounting the number and type of wounds he received. Here, his description has an almost voyeuristic quality in that it seems out of place for someone professing to be a friend of Coriolanus, as Menenius does. This scene is followed shortly by Coriolanus’s public disrobing where he reveals his wounds to the people and asks, as his reward, to be made Consul.

Here are Coriolanus’s most difficult moments. He cannot bear to display himself in such a manner, yet he suffers the indignities of the ceremony. He completes his public humiliation only later to be unable to control his emotions when he is forced to recant his previous positions. Finally, when Sicinius accuses him of being a traitor, it is something he absolutely cannot accept, and so, as ‘Rome’ renounces him, he will renounce Rome.

The sense of “body” can be summed up as follows: the body of Rome is unbalanced. Its various constituent parts are at war with each other. Its arms and legs are at war with its stomach. It is not its head, but, as Menenius suggests, its “great toe” (I.i.155) that leads it—the “lowest, basest, poorest,” (I.i.157-58) member of the body politic. If we see the state of Rome as a “headless” body, unbalanced and (as headless) unreasoning, then we see Coriolanus’s body in contrast. He is not at war with himself. He is intact and complete. He is singular in nature, as Menenius says:

 

…[h]e has been bred i’th’wars

Since he could draw a sword, and is ill school’d

In bolted language; (III i.318-20)

 

Menenius suggests that Coriolanus’s nature is that of a soldier. He is a man of action, not words. In an earlier scene, his fellow general, Cominius, says of Coriolanus that he “rewards / His deeds with doing them, and is content, / To spend the time to end it.” (II.ii.127-29). His reward comes not in the telling of his deeds, nor in the fame that follows, nor in any spoils of war, but rather, his reward is in the doing of them. The reward of being called a hero and having to accept as a laurel the name of the city he has conquered is a burden for Coriolanus. He, Caius Martius is 'rewarded' for conqueoring the enemy city of Corioli by having to be called with the honorific "Coriolanus".( It was common for returning generals after a successful campaign to receive titles that referenced the city or region they conqueored.) 

He would rather act as an instrument of policy or as an anonymous fighter in the battlefield than accept the labels fame presents him. It is interesting to note that in the battle scene with the Volsces at Corioles, he asks his soldiers, “make you a sword of me?” (I.vi.76). He asks to be their weapon, their anonymous tool in battle, to be used in a pure act of noble combat. Honour and title are meaningless to someone like Coriolanus; action is all.

In Rome, the people blame him for policies that cause hardship for the population. And it is true that he has little care for the social classes beneath him. But he also sees his new Consular role as one that must be used as an instrument of aristocratic power; he will carry out the policies of his class. He is fiercely loyal to the nobility and fears a “headless” Rome:

 

To know, when two authorities are up,

Neither supreme, how soon confusion

May enter ‘twixt the gap of both, and take

The one by th’ other. (III.i.109-12)

 

We see Coriolanus intact and ordered in a way that a headless Rome is not. The problem is, that like Titus and Saturninus, Coriolanus is also unbalanced. Both his pride in himself, and his loyalty to the Roman aristocracy are excessive.

Coriolanus's main concern in life is to ensure that he acts the part of a noble warrior, something he has been raised to do all his life. But the bargains he makes as he engages with the ensnaring, layered politics of Rome are intolerable for him. He cannot compromise his ideals and, as such, he is like Titus, clinging to an excessive belief in his honour. In terms of his loyalty to Rome’s aristocracy, he is loyal to an extent even the nobles are uncomfortable with. He clearly identifies himself with the nobility and opposes any concessions to the plebeians:

 

In soothing them we nourish them ‘gainst our Senate

The cockle of rebellion, insolence, sedition,

Which we ourselves have plough’d for, sow’d for and scatter’d[.] (III.i.69-71). 

 

But he can compromise with neither the plebeians nor the aristocracy. His ideal is that the nobility must be held up at all costs, even against the wishes of the nobles, themselves! Coriolanus’s blunt words to the plebeians, and his uncompromising adherence to his principles and beliefs place him in a position where he is forced to leave Rome.

In terms of the system of contrariety, Coriolanus is, like Titus, operating in the abstract. He sees only his own rigid conceptions of loyalty and nobility and, like Titus, such an extreme position will prove fatal for him. Coriolanus is not a tyrant. His actions within Rome are based on his exaggerated sense of order and loyalty. We see such traits as admirable, even desirable in a leader but not to the extent they over-ride all other considerations. When a citizen tells Coriolanus to ask for his boon (his counsulship) “kindly” (II.iii.75), he tells him he asks for too much. Coriolanus is the opposite of "kind". Not only is he ‘unkind’ in the sense that he does not consider himself to be 'of their kind'; he cannot ask for something kindly (i.e., in a friendly, supplicating manner) that he does not want to ask for in the first place.

 

When comparing the body of Coriolanus with the ‘body’ of Rome, we see that both are unbalanced: Coriolanus’s imbalance stems from the singular excess of his noble traits; he is too noble, too loyal, too honourable, etc. The body of Rome, on the other hand, is unbalanced because its traits are too disparate, too individualized and self-centered. As the citizen says in an Act II prose passage:

 

…our wits are so diversely

color’d; and truly I think if all our wits were to issue

out of one skull, they would fly east, west, north, south,

and their consent of one direct way should be at once to

all the points a’ th’ compass. (II.iii.20-24).

 

(Shakespeare provides this passage in prose to suggest the less articulate, less ordered status of the speaker.)

 

To understand further why Coriolanus acts the way he does, I should like to turn to the second major motif of the play, that of “name”. In one of the more peculiar scenes in the play (IV. iii.1-52), a Roman meets a Volscian on a road somewhere between Rome and Antium. Coincidentally, they know each other and remember each other’s names. In the conversation that follows, each reveals to the other the status of their respective cities. The Roman Nicanor reveals to Adrian the Volscian the status of Rome after Coriolanus left. Adrian, in turn, tells of the Volscian level of preparedness in its war with Rome. They then proceed back to the Volsci’s camp for a feast. The scene could be viewed as something of an ‘information’ or ‘transition’ scene to allow Coriolanus time to move to Antium (a segue). However, the significance of this scene comes from the fact that both characters know each other’s name. This scene echoes the earlier Act II scene when Coriolanus asks Cominius for a favour. He wishes to reward a Corioles citizen who has aided him in the war, but when Cominius asks him for the citizen’s name, Coriolanus cannot remember it. The sense is that, for Coriolanus, it is the deed, the doing of the act, that is important, not the individual. In his rigid belief system, to reflect on an action; to name the doer; to label the deed, all take away its essential purity. The act of heroism then becomes the “property” of those who speak of it. This is the reason why Coriolanus is so bitter about the Roman citizens viewing his wounds. They will see them, talk of them, and “use” them for their own purposes. For Coriolanus, his wounds are a part of himself. To use his wounds is to use him.

 

When we examine the actions of Nicanor and Adrian, we see an act of treason. Both betray their cities in a casual, off-hand manner. In fact, the friendliness of their encounter is what helps diffuse or disguise this point. And what are we to make of this scene of friendly treachery? Throughout the first two acts, there are numerous references to the “voices” of the people or their “tongues”. At one point, Coriolanus says he has “fled from words” (II.ii.72). The sense is that words rob actions of their meaning. The words of Nicanor and Adrian “rob” their treason of its meaning. They know each other’s name; therefore they must be friends. As friends, they talk in a friendly manner, but the meaning of their act is still a betrayal. The parallel is made between the physical acts of Coriolanus (and the words that follow) and the traitorous act of the two travellers (and the words that disguise it). We are more understanding of Coriolanus’s mistrust of words after this short but informative scene.

Examining the word “traitor” is helpful to complete our understanding of Coriolanus’s actions. The reasons for his actions are simple enough. They are guided by three basic principles: his loyalty to Rome (as its defender), his loyalty to the aristocracy, and his loyalty to his mother. When Sicinius calls him a traitor in Act III, this proves to be an insult that moves Coriolanus past the bounds of reasoned discourse. His anger takes hold of him and results in his expulsion from the city. The question to ask is why does he react so strongly to this word? The answer is to be found in these three guiding principles upon which he has based his life. By calling him a traitor, by labelling him, by using words that categorize him as disloyal to Rome, Sicinius calls into question Coriolanus’s very existence. Thus, it is no wonder he reacts violently to the accusation. Similarly, in Act V, when Aufidius also calls Coriolanus a traitor, he reacts in an equally uncompromising manner. This time his actions brings about his death.

A contradiction seems to arise at this point. One asks: does Coriolanus, himself, not betray Rome? Is he not, in fact, a traitor? We must again remember the three ordering principles that have guided his life. When Rome banishes him in Act III, two of those three principles are no longer valid (his loyalty to Rome and to its aristocracy). In this respect, Coriolanus is even more inflexible than Titus in his adherence to abstract principles. Both of them show that their belief in ideals is extreme and imbalanced, and they result in actions that reflect the opposite of those ideals (Titus’s cruelty, Coriolanus’s betrayal of Rome). However, Coriolanus’s extreme sense of loyalty is highly personal, whereas Titus’s loyalty extends to tradition with, for example, his respect for the dead, and his concern for his family's name and honour. Coriolanus, on the other hand, is loyal only to those to whom his body serves. Once he has been physically expelled from Rome, the connection is broken. This view of Coriolanus suggests an individual who is profoundly alienated from his society. And he is—except for his connection to his mother.

    "Coriolanus" and "Volumnia"
Where all other persuasions fail, where Coriolanus refuses to let anyone’s “name” persuade him in their pleas for mercy (he “forbade all names” V.i.12.), and where he acts as an instrument of public policy for the Volscians and holds no private audiences (he and Aufidius have led the Volscian army to Rome where he refuses to have private discussions with the frightened Romans), Coriolanus, seeking revenge on the city that rejected him and listening to no others, will at last listen to his mother, and not attack Rome. Shakespeare may be saying that kinship and blood are the only ties that matter, and that the natural “body” of family takes precedence over the body politic.

 There is a contrast between Volumnia’s return in triumph to Rome and Coriolanus’s return to Corioles. In Rome, a Senator shouts as Volumnia enters the city: “Unshout the noise that banish’d Martius! / Repeal him with the welcome of his mother.” (V.v.5). The sense is that, in Rome, Coriolanus is to be remembered in the light of Volumnia’s return and in the acknowledgement that he should not have been banished in the first place. (Those voices that banished him were wrong—they must be “unshout[ed]”.) In the city of Corioles, by contrast, Coriolanus's warlike deeds--against Rome, which he renounced--are recounted. But Aufidius is jealous of the accolades Coriolanus receives from his fellow Volscians and has him assassinated following Aufidius’s accusation that Coriolanus is now a traitor to the Volscian cause. After the murder, Aufidius says Coriolanus, nevertheless, will have a “noble memory” (V.v.153). The sense is he will be remembered differently in Rome than in Corioles, and while he acted the same in both cities, his actions will be remembered differently, depending upon whose words will be used. All his life, Coriolanus wanted actions to speak louder than words, but in the end, it is words that will have the last say. 

In the Act IV scene where Coriolanus arrives in Antium, we witness a different Coriolanus. He reflects on the world. He thinks of friends who were inseparable one minute, and became enemies in the next: “Shall within this hour / On a dissension of a doit, break out / To bitterest enmity” (V.iv.16-18). He thinks of enemies that could become “dearest friends” (V.iv.21). He reflects, in other words, on the contrariness of life, of how it is composed of opposites, and how easily one opposite moves toward the other. When Lucius sought out the Goths in their city in "Titus Andronicus", he was searching, in fact, for his “opposite” to help him achieve a balanced life. Coriolanus’s journey to Antium reflects a similar quest, but there is no opposite there for him to find. Instead, in Aufidius he finds someone much like himself. Aufidius cannot help Coriolanus achieve his equilibrium because Aufidius, like Coriolanus, also believes in a rigid and uncompromising system of honour and nobility; Coriolanus merely transfers his 'system' over to the Volscians. In the end, both Titus and Coriolanus fail to achieve their equilibrium. 

__________________________________________ 

 

* "Titus Andronicus" is only nominally set during a period of the Gothic Invasions. It is not a "history" play in this sense. The specific time frame is unclear but it appears to be in the early Christian era of Roman history, before Christianity became widespread, possibly in the 3rd or 4th Century A.D.

** It is important to remember that Titus's decision to execute only the eldest son of the Goth queen Tamora will have grave repercussions in the future. It is his unbalanced belief in Roman nobility and what you might call 'proper ettiquette' that leads him decide not to kill ALL the Goths he has captured to avenge the deaths of his numerous sons during the wars ("five-and-twenty valiant sons,/Half of the number that King Priam had..." Ii.79-80). His excessive mercy in this case leads to bloody murders later on, with following reprisals in an ever-arcing pendulum of mayhem.)

 

 

Works Cited

 

McAlindon, T. Shakespeare’s Tragic Cosmos. Cambridge:  Cambridge University Press, 1991.

 

Shakespeare, William. "Titus Andronicus" and "Coriolanus" in The Riverside Shakespeare. Ed. G.B. Evans. NY: Houghton Mifflin, 1974.

 

Abrams., M.H., ed. A Glossary of Literary Terms, fifth edition. Fort Worth, Chicago: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc., 1988

 

https://naturalisticpaganism.org/2011/10/27/what-does-responsible-action-mean-to-you/

 

 

Great Chain of Being—"is a hierarchical structure of all matter and life, thought by medieval Christianity to have been decreed by God. The chain begins with God and descends through angels, humans, animals, and plants, to minerals.  It is a concept derived from Plato, Aristotle, and other Greek philosophers, and further developed during the Middle Ages; it reached full expression in early modern Neoplatonism. 

It is credited by the Catholic Church in keeping the peace in Europe for centuries. The very concept of rebellion simply lay outside the reality within which most people lived for to defy the King was to defy God. The Enlightenment broke this supposed divine plan, and fought the last vestiges of feudal hierarchy, by creating secular governmental structures that vested power into the hands of ordinary citizens, rather than in those of divinely ordained monarchs.”  (Wikipedia)

Contrariety"opposition or inconsistency between two things” (O.E.D.)

Responsible Action—“It affirmed that humanity has both the capability and the responsibility to meet our challenges without recourse to supernatural aid…The question for today is: within what larger contexts ought we be responsible?  To whom or what are you responsible?” (Naturalistic)

Tribune—an official in ancient Rome chosen by the plebeians to protect their interests.

Consul—the highest elected political office of the Roman Republic (509 to 27 BC), Each year, the citizens of Rome elected two consuls to serve jointly for a one-year term. There were two consuls to create a check on the power of any individual. After the establishment of the Empire (27 BC), the consuls became mere symbolic representatives of Rome's republican heritage and held little power and authority, with the Emperor acting as the supreme authority. (Wikipedia)

Gothic Wars—were a long series of conflicts against the Roman Empire between the years 249 and 554.

Revenge Tragedy—"is derived from Seneca’s favorite materials of murder, revenge, ghosts, mutilation, and carnage with most acts done off-stage…Elizabethan writers had them acted out on stage to satisfy the audience’s appetite for violence and horror.” (Glossary)

Morality Plays and Mystery Cycle Plays—Popular from the 9th to 15th centuries; unknown authorships, originating within the church as dramatizations as part of the Latin liturgical services; eventually local guild societies would put on cycles of plays during major holy day events (i.e., Christmas, Lent, etc.), some at fixed stations, others on movable “pageant wagons”. Morality plays were “dramatized allegories of representative Christian life. “Everyman” and “Mankind” were characters in plays, for example. (Glossary)


 

 


 

 

Prof comments: GRADE=A-

A very interesting analysis of the two plays. I'm not equally convinced by all points of it, but I think you tackle some extremely interesting issues, and have some subtle insights into the dialectics of the 2 plays. I phoned you when I got your message--but you weren't there--to say that I've put your name forward for consideration for the English essay prize. You will be no doubt being contacted by Mrs. Thomas about this soon; hang on to the essay!

 

 

 

 

No comments: